A linguistic expression may be motivated or arbitrary. This concerns the relationship of the significans to the significatum. The significans and its structure may be partly motivated by the significatum and its structure. This entails that speaker and hearer do not, to this extent, need to know the particular language system to form the sign, as its significans is partly predictable on the basis of its significatum, and vice versa.

Again, the relationship between significans and significatum may be partly arbitrary. This means that the significans has properties which are not predictable on the basis of the significatum, and vice versa. Instead, they derive from constraints of the particular language system which concern the formation of signs in this language.

Motivation and arbitrariness are relevant at two different levels of the formation of linguistic signs. At the lower level, the significans of a simple sign (a morpheme or root) is combined with its significatum. This association is arbitrary for most simple signs. Only to some extent does motivation come in by onomatopoeia and sound symbolism. At the higher level, a (presumably complex) meaning is coded by a complex sign, i.e., a morphological or syntactic construction. Here the hierarchy of complexity levels of linguistic structure comes in:

Hierarchy of complexity levels of linguistic structure
levelunitlinguistic operations
discoursetextrhetorical operations
syntaxcomplex clausesyntactic operations
simple clause
syntagma
morphologyword forminflectional operations
stemoperations of stem formation
morpheme/root[none]

Constraints of the language system are the stricter, the lower the level of structure. Specifically, at the highest level, few operations are specific to the language used and subject to its constraints. At the lowest level of structure, i.e. the morphological level, obligatoriness prevails, i.e. the formation of units is largely dictated by language-specific constraints. Again, the constraints at the highest level are relatively transparent to motivation, while the constraints at the lowest level may be completely arbitrary.

For illustration, imagine a situation where the speaker has solved the task of associating significans with significatum at the lowest level of the preceding diagram; i.e., he knows the elementary words of the language he must speak. That is all he knows; he does not know a single rule of its grammar. In an emergency situation, he may produce a.

.a.Daughter sick — daughter physician need urgent.
b.My daughter is sick; she needs a physician urgently.

Observe that a may be completely appropriate in the speech situation and may be perfectly intelligible. What the speaker has done is apply operations of the uppermost level of the hierarchy of complexity levels to the vocables he knows. His utterance does have a structure; but it reflects the structure of his thought without regard to any linguistic constraints.

Now compare with this the English version in b. The following of its features derive from constraints specific to this language:

The following aspects of this example instantiate general principles:

In the last instance, a rule of grammar can be arbitrary to the point of producing a counter-iconic configuration. One such example is provided by the 3rd person singular suffix in b, which runs counter to well-motivated principles of markedness theory. Another is the definite article introducing the relative pronoun el que 'who/which' in Spanish, which does not relate to any determination in semantic terms, much less a definite determination ().

.setratadeunosasuntossobrelosqueexistenpocosestudios
SpanREFLtreatsofINDF:M.PLmatter(M):PL[onDEF:M.PLSRexist:3.PLfew studies]
we are dealing with matters on which little research has been done
(Boletín Oficial del Parlamento de Andalucía 2015/79: 131)

There is, thus, a certain correlation between decreasing complexity level and decreasing motivation – thus, increasing arbitrariness. The lowest complexity level is the level of the single morpheme or root; and this is where arbitrariness prevails. The freedom of choice for the speaker decreases with the complexity level. Where the speaker has a choice, his choice will be motivated by the structure of his message. If the speaker cannot choose what to say, then the structure of what he must say, anyway, does not need to be motivated. Other considerations including shortness and increase of redundancy then prevail.